Developmental Plasticity and the “Hard-Wired” Problem


“Development is the missing link between genotype and phenotype, a place too often occupied by metaphors in the past … But a strong emphasis on the genome means that environmental influence is systematically ignored. If you begin with DNA and view development as “hard-wired,” you overlook the flexible phenotype and the causes of its variation that are the mainsprings of adaptive evolution.” (Mary Jane West-Eberhard, 2003: 89-90)

“Genes, unlike gods, are conditional. They are exquisitely good at simple if-then logic: if in a certain environment, then develop in a certain way… So here is the first moral of the tale: Don’t be frightened of genes. They are not gods; they are cogs. (Matt Ridley, 2003: 250)

 

Plasticity: actor Christian Bale at two points in time. Same genes, different phenotypes.

Plasticity: actor Christian Bale at two points in time. Same genes, different phenotypes.

In his book The Triple Helix, Richard Lewontin told the story of the molecular biologist and Nobel laureate Sydney Brenner, who – while speaking at a conference – predicted that one day we would be able to “compute” an organism (2002). All we would need are two things: the organism’s full genome and powerful enough computers that were up to the task.

The idea is seductive. Genes are sometimes seen as self-sufficient molecules, almost existing in a vacuum, that contain all the information necessary to code for proteins. From there, it’s not a very big logical leap to think that if you had the genome, you could enter the code in some database, hit “run,” and then watch some digitized version of the organism unfold.

In fact, scientists are doing something much like this for the tiny roundworm C. elegans with the project OpenWorm. Yet even for a relatively simple organism such as this, with only about a thousand cells in total, there are reasons to be cautious. As The Economist warned in its write-up of OpenWorm: “Attempting to simulate everything faithfully would bring even a supercomputer to its knees.” However, this isn’t due solely to the limits of computing power (what if we had a super-duper computer!?). Rather, it’s a matter of how the question is framed.

To go back to Brenner, I don’t know what else he said that day, so it isn’t fair to caricature the rest of his comments as quite so reductionist. If asked, I think he would acknowledge that if we play the scenario out, we are immediately confronted by the fact that there is no vacuum. All organisms must reside somewhere, or – more realistically – many somewheres over a lifetime. And, whatever the genome is, environmental circumstances can have profound influences on phenotypes.

 

“The Environment”

“There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are dreamt of in your database.”

 

Here is a straightforward example. Barry Bogin and Ines Varela Silva found that ethnic Maya children residing in Los Angeles and Florida were on average 11.5 centimeters (4.5 inches) taller than those who lived in Guatemala (Bogin et al 2002). This was one of the largest population shifts in height ever recorded in that short a period of time (for those in the US, most of their parents had migrated only within the last 20 years). In fact, the heights of Maya children in the US were not significantly different from American reference data, despite their being perceived as genetically ‘short.’

Changing growth patterns in Maya children. (z-scores nearer to zero are approaching the average US child).

Changing growth patterns in Maya children. (z-scores nearer to zero are approaching the average US child).

 

On the other hand, body build (the proportion of total height that was due to leg length) did not change much. Some studies have in fact found that average body proportions can change in a generation or two, such as in the case of Japan (Tanner et al 1982), but there are reasons that this pattern is inconsistent across studies. Phenotypes are not necessarily set in stone, though some may be more responsive to change than others depending on the age of exposure, and degree of severity, to different environmental variables.

What accounts for the difference in height in the Maya? We can dismiss the idea of a selective migration effect – that the tallest decided to migrate to the US, while shorter ones remained in Guatemala. That possibility seems highly unlikely, as most entered the US following indiscriminate forced displacement during a bloody, decade-long civil war. Another strike against that explanation is that heights of US Maya were even closer to US reference values in 2000 than they were in 1992, indicating an incremental shift in growth patterns. Instead, the authors suggested that the differences were likely due to factors such as nutrition, health care, and the quality of drinking water in the US compared to Guatemala. This is consistent with research demonstrating changes in growth patterns in many populations over time (Bogin 1999; Steckel and Rose 2002).

Certainly, genes are an important source of variation in traits like height, but this is complex, with many genes involved. One of the first to be consistently associated with variations in height across populations (the UK, Sweden and Finland), as well as in adults and children, was reported in 2007 (Weedon et al 2007). However, the effects were modest. Having one copy of a particular allele was roughly equal to an additional 0.4 cm in adult stature, accounting for only about 0.3% of the total variation observed.

What accounts for the rest? There must be other genes involved, but across the globe, several studies have found correlations between many environmental variables – large and small – with how a fetus, infant, or child physically develops. This is true not only for height, but for things like adiposity and overall health. I’m going to group these together, not to imply they are all equivalent, but only because they all deal with somatic development and it would be too cumbersome to treat them all separately:

  • altitude (Greska 1990)
  • seasonality (Little et al 1993)
  • pollutants (Schell et al 2012)
  • religious food restrictions such as during Ramadan (Reiches et al 2014)
  • socioeconomic status (Leatherman et al 1995)
  • neighborhood wealth (Drewnowski et al 2007)
  • homelessness/availability of shelter (Smith & Richards 2008)
  • number of siblings (Ochiai et al 2012)
  • infectious diseases (Moore et al 2001)
  • maternal nutrition during pregnancy (Barker 1998)
  • maternal smoking during pregnancy (von Kries et al 2002)
  • maternal nutrition as a child (Stein et al 2004)
  • whether one’s mother was a twin or triplet (if you’re a marmoset; Rutherford et al 2014)
  • grandmother’s exposure to famine (Stein and Lumey 2000)
  • psychological stress (Gohlke et al 2004)
  • our gut microbiota (Turnbaugh et al 2006)
  • amount of sleep (Taveras et al 2014)
  • physical activity levels (Cardoso and Garcia 2009)
  • political instability and war (Clarkin 2012; Devakumar et al 2014)
  • cultural beliefs about food and household distribution of resources (Dettwyler 1993)

This is just a partial list; a complete one is probably an exercise in futility. One of my advisors in graduate school, Gary James, liked to say that “the best model of reality is reality itself.” What he meant was that we can never account for all of the variables that influence our biology. We can pick out a few major ones, but it’s beyond our capacity to model everything, even for a simple organism like C. elegans. This doesn’t mean we can’t know anything; otherwise what’s the point? In fact, we know a great deal about growth and development. It’s just a reminder about the complexity of organisms, and how many moving pieces there are.

 

Seamless and Inseparable

 “What is inherited is DNA. Everything else is developed.” – James Tanner, “Foetus Into Man” (1990 :119)

 

As nearly everyone would acknowledge, BOTH genetics and environment are essential, not because one is more important than the other, but because the two are inextricably intertwined. There is no organism without a genome; but there is also no such thing as an organism without an environment.

This also puts a serious damper on the idea of ‘computing’ organisms based solely on genomes, at least not in any absolute sense. If you had the complete genome of an extinct mammoth, and could somehow find it a suitable place to gestate and then find someone to care for it until maturity, you’d get something we would identify as a mammoth, rather than, say, a jellyfish. But to fully account for its individual biology – what kind of mammoth or jellyfish would we get – we would need much more than the genome. We would also need a crystal ball to predict all future environmental variables the organism would ever encounter.

Speaking of jellyfish, if you grow one in space, you will still get a jellyfish. But without being exposed to gravity in the early stages of its life, even for a few days, there is a decent chance that they will move abnormally once they’ve returned to earth (Spangenberg et al 1994). Of course, most jellyfish will never experience space, but the point is that being able to navigate something even as basic as gravity does not come automatically, but may require exposure to it.

We’re then forced to confront the reality that the effects of the environment on development are not merely noise interfering with the ‘true’ nature of the organism. They are integral. It makes sense that jellyfish genomes should ‘expect’ gravity because, before space travel, it had never been otherwise in the billions of years of life on earth. In other words, genomes are sculpted by natural selection to navigate probable environments, but with some degree of unpredictability. The same is true for us. As the developmental psychologist Michael Tomasello once said: “Fish are born expecting water, and humans are born expecting culture.”

One problem is that we often remain stuck in dichotomous “nature versus nurture” thinking. Some of us lean more toward one side than another, depending on the biological trait in question, but as Anne Fausto-Sterling warned, that view is too simplistic:

Most people have only one model to think about how human traits develop. Whether they call themselves determinists or constructionists, nativists or empiricists; whether they emphasize genes or environment, nature or nurture, or think of important traits as hardwired or plastic, they envision a seesaw. Sometimes nature (genes, wiring, etc.) is heavier, and the seesaw bounces onto nature’s ground. Sometimes the environment (culture, nurture) is heavier and weighs down that end of the seesaw. Frustratingly, even though a process approach to understanding motor development is pretty much settled science, in most other arenas (sex differences, intelligence, athletic and musical ability, and more), people can’t stop arguing—adding a little weight to one side or there to the other—and the seesaw teeters back and forth with each new research finding.

But there is no seesaw. Human behaviors are not “things” more or less influenced by one or another source. They are processes that are simultaneously embodied and shaped by experience. The behavior of walking, as just one example, differs from one individual to the next depending on health history, body size and shape (for example, limb-to-trunk length ratios), past physical experience, the character of the walking surface, clothing, and many other factors.

An emphasis on development as a process underscores how interwoven nature and nurture are. Perhaps this concept doesn’t come easily to us, in part, because time is invisible. But it helps to reflect on the obvious fact that we aren’t born fully-formed. Rather, all organisms grow into maturity, responding to stimuli and challenges, while exchanging matter and energy with the world around us. And as humans, we can take a rather long time to develop into maturity.

As we grow, we incorporate our environmental circumstances. Researchers have given this idea different names such as ‘embodiment’ (Krieger 2005), experiences getting ‘under the skin,’ racial inequalities ‘becoming biology’ (Gravlee 2009), or culture becoming ‘en-brained’ throughout our lives (Downey and Lende 2012: 32). And though I have to admit that I never quite got what Pierre Bourdieu was trying to say, I do remember liking his phrase ‘the internalization of externality.’ In subtle and not-so-subtle ways, our outsides get in our insides. And, sometimes it can seem like everything in our inside wants to be on our outside. Insides and outsides may be in more intimate contact than we are sometimes aware.

The internalization of externality. Source.

The internalization of externality: a tree incorporating a bicycle over the years. Source.

On a personal note, when I look at my young children now, of course I see their current selves. Even as a father who has been present for nearly every day of their lives, it can be hard to remember how much they’ve changed in appearance and behavior in only a few short years. Their present selves might be even more different, had their past selves contracted a nasty infection, attended a different school, etc. Each transient state impacts the next, with the earliest ones having a disparate effect on all the subsequent ones.

Some have emphasized the importance of the first 1,000 days as a critical period of life. There’s nothing magical about 1,000 days, but it’s a good approximation of when our development is most vulnerable, and when our developmental trajectory is most alterable, depending on what part of our biology we’re talking about. Of course, events later in life can also have profound effects. Rachel Yehuda and Linda Bierer (2009) have referred to the development of post-traumatic stress disorder as akin to an ‘existential transformation.’ In a way, falling in love is also transformational, at least for prairie voles. There are cultural examples too. Someone who has undergone a rite of passage – an initiation, marriage, a rise in rank – is often conferred a new status and set of rights and responsibilities (van Gennep 1960). A person (or vole) who has fallen in love, been initiated into a society as an adult, or diagnosed with PTSD is obviously still the same person they were before. Yet, in another sense they can also be seen as qualitatively different.

 

Hardwired for Plasticity

Over at The Mermaid’s Tale, Ken Weiss once wrote that “we are hard-wired not to be hard-wired” for our behavioral repertoire. Bill Leonard and colleagues made a similar claim about our diet: that we were selected to be flexible omnivores, rather than to have a highly specialized dietary niche (Leonard et al 2010). As Matt Ridley succinctly put it, plasticity is evolution’s “masterstroke” (2003:174).

This brings us to a fundamental question: how does a genome accommodate so much unpredictable environmental complexity? In a nutshell, plasticity. Variants of genes (alleles) that thrive in given set of ecological conditions will be passed on at higher rates than others. But this is not the only force affecting allele frequencies; nor is it the only way to adapt. I once heard the biological anthropologist R. Brooke Thomas say that, without a doubt, natural selection was an essential mechanism in shaping our biology. However, he also felt it was “too clunky” to try to explain all variation and adaptation. And he was right.

Genetic adaptations certainly exist. But a genome that can respond to environmental feedback and operate in many possible, unpredictable conditions could be even more likely to survive and reproduce than a rigid one, hardwired to just do its thing regardless of circumstances. Sometimes those responses are due to developmental constraints; sometimes they result in pathologies; and other times they may be truly adaptive. Though it’s not always easy to differentiate between them (Ellison and Jasienska 2007).

Take body temperature regulation, for example. There do seem to be genetic adaptations for this across human populations. Near the equator, body builds tend to be thinner and longer-limbed – on average – in order to dissipate heat more easily. But this has always been a very imperfect correlation, and there are exceptions to this trend. The strength of this association has also weakened in recent decades, as globalization and changes in diet and activity patterns have affected patterns of body mass around the world (Katzmarzyk and Leonard 1998). Rather than relying solely on body build to regulate temperature, there are other levels of adaptation (Frisancho 1993):

  • Behavioral: Is it hot out? Go find some shade.
  • Cultural: Are you cold? Build a fire. Put on a parka.
  • Physiological: Sweating, shivering. Vasodilation/vasconstriction.
  • Developmental: Older Quechua in high-altitude Peru are more resistant to cold than young Quechua, as they had more time to develop under cold conditions (Little et al 1971).

All of these adaptations take place on different timescales. Whereas natural selection takes generations, by definition, behaviors can take just a few seconds. Developmental adaptations occur while the organism is growing, and may take years, but this is still within a single lifetime. Finally, there may be another, intermediate level of adaptation, which Chris Kuzawa referred to as “phenotypic inertia” (Kuzawa 2005).

It’s an intriguing idea. Kuzawa hypothesized that: “As a mode of adaptation, phenotypic inertia may help the organism cope with ecologic trends too gradual to be tracked by conventional developmental plasticity, but too rapid to be tracked by natural selection.” In other words, the experiences of parental generations can carry over, perhaps by developmental constraint, perhaps epigenetically (yes, I realize that word is overused).

Last example. Stewart et al (1980) conducted an experiment where one group of rats was given a low protein diet for ten to twelve generations, while a control group was given a normal diet. At the end of that time, the poor-diet group weighed about half of what the controls did by adulthood. When the researchers tried to rehabilitate the poor-diet lineage by re-introducing a normal diet, some interesting patterns emerged.

First, timing was important, and the earlier the rehabilitation, the better the results. Rats given good diets after weaning did not fare as well in terms of physical growth as those who were given good diets in infancy (‘cross-fostered’ to control mothers at birth) or in utero. Second, full recovery took two to three generations in both of the groups that were rehabilitated postnatally. One generation was not sufficient. By comparison, the prenatally rehabilitated group actually overshot the growth seen in the control group, after which they came back to ‘normal’ by generation three.

Finally, the low protein group also suffered in terms of learning (a Lashley jumping platform test). Many never achieved complete proficiency on the various tests, which consisted of choosing between and jumping through one of two doors. By contrast, 100% of the control group did so, and in many fewer trials (average of 170 vs. 230). For the rehabbed offspring, those well-fed after weaning showed no improvement (230 trials), while the early postnatal (190) and prenatal groups (210) fared slightly better, though they never caught up completely, at least not within three generations.  

So where does this leave us? Stewart et al. hedged somewhat against making superficial comparisons between their study on rats and humans, but they also suggested there could be parallels with deprived populations, such as in developing countries facing generations of poverty. Recovery might not happen right away in terms of growth or learning, even if nutritional quality (or other factors) change radically.    

We can say, then, that of course genes matter tremendously, but so does the environment. And “the environment” does not begin in kindergarten, at birth, or even prenatally. The experiences of previous generations may also leave a mark. In truth, it all counts, and for fundamental biological reasons. I’ll end with Matt Ridley:

It is genes that allow the human mind to learn, to remember, to imitate, to imprint, to absorb culture, and to express instincts. Genes are not puppet masters or blueprints. Nor are they just the carriers of heredity. They are active during life; they switch on and off; they respond to the environment…They are both cause and consequence of our actions. Somehow the adherents of the “nurture” side of the argument have scared themselves silly at the power and inevitability of genes and missed the greatest lesson of all: the genes are on their side.” (2003: 6)

 

 

References

Barker DJP. 1998Mothers, Babies and Health in Later Life. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone. Link

Bogin B. 1999. Patterns of Human Growth. Cambridge. Link

Bogin B, Smith P, Orden AB, Varela Silva MI, Loucky J.  2002. Rapid change in height and body proportions of Maya American children. Am J Hum Biol. 14(6):753-61. Link

Cardoso HF, Garcia S. 2009. The Not-so-Dark Ages: ecology for human growth in medieval and early twentieth century Portugal as inferred from skeletal growth profiles. Am J Phys Anthropol 138(2):136-47. Link

Clarkin PF. 2012. War, forced displacement and growth in Laotian adults. Ann Hum Biol. 39(1):36-45. Link

Dettwyler KM. 1993. Dancing Skeletons: Life and Death in West Africa. Waveland. Link

Devakumar D, Birch M, Osrin D, Sondorp E, Wells JCK. 2014. The intergenerational effects of war on the health of children. BMC Medicine 12:57 Link

Downey G, Lende DH. 2012. Neuroanthropology and the encultured brain. In Lende DH, Downey G (eds.) The Encultured Brain p. 23-65. Cambridge: MIT. Link

Drewnowski A, Rehm CD, Solet D. 2007. Disparities in obesity rates: Analysis by ZIP code area. Social Science & Medicine 65 (12): 2458-63. Link

Ellison PT, Jasienska G. 2007. Constraint, pathology, and adaptation: how can we tell them apart? Am J Hum Biol. 19(5):622-30. Link

Frisancho AR. 1993. Human Adaptation and Accommodation. U Michigan. Link

Gohlke BC, Frazer FL, Stanhope R. 2004. Growth hormone secretion and long-term growth data in children with psychosocial short stature treated by different changes in environment. J Pediatr Endocrinol Metab 17:637–643. Link

Gravlee CC. 2009. How race becomes biology: embodiment of social inequality. Am J Phys Anthropol. 139(1):47-57. Link

Greska LP. 1990. Developmental responses to high-altitude hypoxia in Bolivian children of European ancestry: A test of the developmental adaptation hypothesis. American Journal of Human Biology 2(6): 603–12 Link

Katzmarzyk PT1, Leonard WR. 1998. Climatic influences on human body size and proportions: ecological adaptations and secular trends. Am J Phys Anthropol. 106(4):483-503. Link

Krieger N. 2005. Embodiment: a conceptual glossary for epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health 59(5): 350–355. Link

Kuzawa CW. 2005. Fetal origins of developmental plasticity: are fetal cues reliable predictors of future nutritional environments? American Journal of Human Biology 17: 5-21. Link

Leatherman TL, Carey JW, Thomas RB. 1995. Socioeconomic change and patterns of growth in the Andes. Am J Phys Anthropol. 97(3):307-21. Link

Leonard WR, Stock JT, Valeggia CR. 2010. Evolutionary perspectives on human diet and nutrition. Evolutionary Anthropology 19:85–86. Link

Lewontin R. 2002. The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism, and Environment. Harvard. Link

Little MA, Thomas RB, Mazess RB, Baker PT. 1971. Population differences and developmental changes in extremity temperature responses to cold among Andean Indians. Human Biology 43(1): 70-91. Link

Little MA, Gray SJ, Leslie PW. 1993. Growth of nomadic and settled Turkana infants of northwest Kenya.  Am J Phys Anthropol. 92(3):273-89. Link

Moore SR, Lima AA, Conaway MR, Schorling JB, Soares AM, Guerrant RL. 2001. Early childhood diarrhoea and helminthiases associate with long-term linear growth faltering. Int J Epidemiol. 2001 30(6):1457-64. Link

Ochiai H, Shirasawa T, Ohtsu T, Nishimura R, Morimoto A, Obuchi R, Hoshino H, Tajima N, Kokaze A. 2012. Number of siblings, birth order, and childhood overweight: a population-based cross-sectional study in Japan. BMC Public Health 12:766. Link

Reiches MW, Moore SE, Prentice AM, Ellison PT. 2014. Endocrine responses, weight change, and energy sparing mechanisms during Ramadan among Gambian adolescent women. Am J Hum Biol 26(3):395-400. Link

Ridley M. 2003. Nature Via Nurture: Genes, Experience, and What Makes Us Human. New York: Harper Collins. Link

Rutherford JN, deMartelly VA, Layne Colon DG, Ross CN, Tardif SD. 2014. Developmental origins of pregnancy loss in the adult female common marmoset monkey (Callithrix jacchus). PLoS One.  28;9(5):e96845. Link

Schell LM, Burnitz KK, Gallo MV. 2012. Growth as a mirror: is endocrine disruption challenging Tanner’s concept? Ann Hum Biol. 39(5):361-71. Link

Smith C, Richards R. 2008. Dietary intake, overweight status, and perceptions of food insecurity among homeless Minnesotan youth. Am J Hum Biol. 20(5):550-63. Link

Spangenberg DB, Jernigan T, McCombs R, Lowe BT, Sampson M, Slusser J. 1994.  Development studies of Aurelia (Jellyfish) ephyrae which developed during the SLS-1 mission. Advances in Space Research 14 (8):239–47. Link

Steckel RH and Rose JC. 2002. The Backbone of History: Health and Nutrition in the Western Hemisphere. Cambridge University Press. Link

Stein AD, Barnhart HX, Wang M, Hoshen MB, Ologoudou K, Ramakrishnan U, Grajeda R, Ramirez-Zea M, Martorell R. 2004. Comparison of linear growth patterns in the first three years of life across two generations in Guatemala. Pediatrics 113(3 Pt 1):e270-5. Link

Stein AD, Lumey LH. 2000. The relationship between maternal and offspring birth weights after maternal prenatal famine exposure: the Dutch Famine Birth Cohort Study. Hum Biol 72:641–654. Link

Stewart RJC, Sheppard H, Preece R, Waterlow JC. 1980. The effect of rehabilitation at different stages of development of rats marginally malnourished for ten to twelve generations. British Journal of Nutrition 43: 403-11. Link

Tanner JM. 1990. Foetus Into Man: Physical Growth from Conception to Maturity. Harvard. Link 

Tanner JM, Hayashi T, Preece MA, Cameron N. 1982. Increase in length of leg relative to trunk in Japanese children and adults from 1957 to 1977: comparison with British and with Japanese Americans. Annals of Human Biology 9: 411–23. Link

Taveras EM, Gillman MW, Peña MM, Redline S, Rifas-Shiman SL. 2014. Chronic Sleep Curtailment and Adiposity. Pediatrics doi:10.1542/peds.2013-3065 Link

Turnbaugh PJ, Ley RE, Mahowald MA, Magrini V, Mardis ER, Gordon JI. 2006. An obesity-associated gut microbiome with increased capacity for energy harvest. Nature. 444(7122):1027-31. Link

van Gennep A. 1960. The Rites of Passage. Psychology Press. Link

von Kries R, Toschke AM, Koletzko B, Slikker W Jr. 2002. Maternal smoking during pregnancy and childhood obesity. Am J Epidemiol 156(10):954-61. Link

Weedon et al. 2007. A common variant of HMGA2 is associated with adult and childhood height in the general population. Nature Genetics 39 (10): 1245-50. Link

West-Eberhard MJ. 2003. Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. Oxford Link

Yehuda R, Bierer LM. 2009. The relevance of epigenetics to PTSD: implications for the DSM-V. J Trauma Stress. 22(5):427-34. Link

 

 

54 thoughts on “Developmental Plasticity and the “Hard-Wired” Problem

  1. A nice treatment of the subject. A visit to a medieval armament museum in Europe shows the same thing seen in the Maya (and similarly in Japan since WWII), where nobody could argue differential migration was responsible.

    If we accepted the (as I would say) prior likelihood that low rather than high levels of genomic hardwiring would make species more likely to persist, we might view things very differently, and then face the challenge to try to explain how on earth ‘genes’ (DNA sequences) could achieve that.

    In addition, we might then find situations in which hardwiring might be better–in very rapidly proliferating widely dispersed species like bacteria? In very stable environments (or in traits affected by very stable aspects of the environment)?

    That would turn Just-So story-telling, on both sides of the environment-genome divide, into actual science.

    • Hi Ken, thanks for that. Yes, there are definitely plenty of other studies of changing growth patterns over time in the same place, eliminating the possible confounder of selective migration. Japan is one, as are many European countries too. Sometimes populations get taller, but it can of course go the other way when conditions are not conducive to growth.

      Again, Japan fits here. The average Japanese child was getting taller than their predecessor generations before WWII, then dropped dramatically during and just after the war, only to bounce back afterwards.

  2. Pingback: Hard-Wired to NOT Be Hard-Wired – Pat Clarkin on Our Marvelous Flexibility | Neuron Culture

  3. Pingback: From the Blogosphere: Nature versus Nurture | The Opposing Thumb

  4. Pingback: Developmental Plasticity and the “Hard-Wired” Problem | Urban Watershed Management & Biodiversity 2014

  5. It’s important to look at development as a process not a result or outcomes. In nowadays research, when we do GWAS or transcriptome sequencing, we actually believe the difference between ‘ normal’ phenotype and ‘abnormal’ ones give us a path to the cure. However, we forgot genes are active, Genomic DNA, RNA, small RNA are actively seconding to the environmental influences, as well as some other unknown factors. Too much we confidently photo the research and give a ‘solid’ conclusion. The next second after we step forward bit, we found we are ‘wrong’. Development process is a good point to rethink of all these fundamental questions, gene, eviromental reality. Maybe as well as our current research life science which is putting more weight on directing us living a ‘normal’ life. Well done, mate.

  6. I just want to know where the ‘tree incorporating the bike’ is located. I want to see that! Great post on developmental plasticity too!

  7. I’m not in the field, and so I’ve been decades behind, I still thought there was a nature VS Nurture argument going on – well there is, among the less educated, like myself. I have been identifying as “a Nurture guy” my whole adult life, largely because of an obsession I have with an insight I had regarding the use of punishment generally, but for the purposes of this conversation, I’d rather say it’s because Nurture is what is in our control, that we can change what we do with less intrusive methods than stuffing our Natures, our genes, into some rigid breeding scheme.

    The famous twin studies drove me crazy (and any other lay “Nurture” person, I imagine), mostly because I heard so much about them from arguing with racists online, people mostly as unconnected to science as I am, and they hold up the twin studies as proof of the “Nature” side of the argument. On the surface, those studies appear to destroy Nurture as the more important principle, but a conversation I got into recently with someone ( a smarter someone than most of my online conversations – they’re here on WP – Ad Nausica) helped me realize something. I was trying to find my way back to a rational belief in Nurture as “what matters,” and I think I have. I was theorizing that the twin studies measure genetics VS environment – but there is an underlying assumption there, I think, the assumption that a different family in a different town signifies a significantly different environment.

    I had a lot of conjecture (I call it “reason” and “logic) as to why different families in different towns were in fact very similar environments, but the penny finally dropped, and I think I understand:

    the interaction of genes and environment and the sometimes amazing similarities in the lives of these separated twins that the studies looked at actually proves the point, doesn’t it?

    Considering that it probably requires that BOTH genes and environment to be very similar to produce such correlations as the twin studies boast, then the environments of these children must really be very similar indeed. I think this proves that very many people, at least in the European culture and its offspring in North America, all provide the same environment for their kids.

    So . . . am I crazy? Please show me what is right or wrong in this reasoning. I’m sure you can tell, my focus is child-rearing, and this could be an important link in my chain of thought about it.

    I appreciate your patience . . .

    Jeff

    • Hi Jeff,

      No patience necessary, and you are not crazy. These are important questions, and frankly I’m not sure I can answer them adequately or without stepping on a few landmines. Let me quote Ridley again (if you’re keeping score, that’s four quotes from him, so I recommend his book. It’s a bit out of date now, but accessible and insightful). He wrote:

      “Nurture is reversible; nature is not. That is the reason responsible intellectuals have spent a century preferring the cheerful meliorism of environment to the bleak Calvinism of genes.”

      I think this gets at a lot of what people are arguing about. For those who emphasize only one end of the spectrum (nature people or nurture people), they are often not arguing about science. Instead, it seems to come down to “could the world we inhabit be any different” in terms of the social standing of individuals (or groups).

      By the way, Ridley wasn’t being serious. He was just saying that nature and nurture are often (inevitably?) politicized. Sometimes hardline nurture people want to wish away the idea that some things are not in our control. OTOH, hardline nature people sometimes see the world as inevitable, where only genes count. The reality is that everything counts and it’s all tied together. And there are environmental factors that can be irreversible (or nearly so), such as contracting polio leading to paralysis or some traumatic event like child abuse having long-term psychological effects. On the other hand, some genetic factors can be worked around. If you have a genetic predisposition to PKU, you can modify your diet. So genetic is not always ‘inevitable.’

      I don’t think anybody truly sits at the either extreme end of the spectrum. Most people would acknowledge that plasticity exists, but they seem to disagree about how much, depending on the trait in question and the environmental circumstances. It’s complex.

      • Not touching it, huh? LOL. I forgot to say, a great post., very clear and informative, even for non-scientists.
        OK, I’m going to consider that the rules of court apply, that silence indicates assent (as well as the internet rule that silence indicates victory!), and go ahead and keep thinking what I was thinking – surprise, surprise . . .
        Of course I don’t blame anyone for not weighing in on the social implications, “minefield” really is a great description of that world. Thank you for the bit of validation. I think this idea is going to flavour much of my thought and blogging on my favourite subject (punishment, mainly in child-rearing but also in adult situations, criminal justice) going forward . . . just one more question:

        has this basic principle gotten any attention in the field you’re in, or in related fields, that you know of, that correlations shown in genetics must also mean correlation of environment?

        Thanks Patrick,

        Jeff

        • happy to report a few years have passed and I’ve gotten past Pinker, etc. I’m a massive Trivers fan, is the thing – but he’s not up to speed with my obsession either. Mostly I’m a me fan. It was fun looking back at this, and I still like my point about the twin studies: if the phenotype is the same, then BOTH genes and environment were the same, had to have been.

  8. How profound: genes are on our side! That one’s ‘environment’ may have lingering and multi-generational effects on development… this makes sense to me when I consider your rat example and some of the more extreme examples (a woman/man exposed to toxins/radiation as a child thus creating birth defects among their offspring)… but it makes me wonder how subtle the long-lasting influences of one’s environment may be… and the consequences/outcomes for the future generations (physically, psychologically, etc). Just pondering…

  9. As I was reading, I couldn’t help but think about Robert Sapolsky’s reply to “The Edge’s” annual question “What Scientific Idea is Ready for Retirement?” (http://edge.org/annual-questions). His reply resonates with your point, that without an environment there are no organisms. Sapolsky goes so far as to say that the entire notion of “gene X environment interaction” is misguided, in that when one considers the possibility of an interaction, that opens the door for also considering “main effects” in isolation. But when it comes to nature and nurture, without nurture (i.e., environment) there is no nature. Logically then, its not an interaction we are looking at, when we look at the development of organisms. Rather, the developmental mechanism is one multi-component package containing genes that exist and unfold in contexts. You can find Sapolsky’s remarks here: http://edge.org/responses/what-scientific-idea-is-ready-for-retirement. Worth a read.

    Great information and examples, here. I appreciate the efforts and make a point in relevant classes (intro to psychology, developmental psychology) to let students in on the well kept secret that the nature – nurture debate is dead, and refer them to Matt Ridley’s book too. Now i have some more examples too – thanks!

    • Thanks, Erica. I just checked out the Sapolsky piece and liked it a lot:

      “My problem with the concept is with the particularist use of “a” gene-environment interaction, the notion that there can be one. This is because, at the most benign, this implies that there can be cases where there aren’t gene-environment interactions. Worse, that those cases are in the majority. Worst, the notion that lurking out there is something akin to a Platonic ideal as to every gene’s actions—that any given gene has an idealized effect, that it consistently “does” that, and that circumstances where that does not occur are rare and represent either pathological situations or inconsequential specialty acts. Thus, a particular gene may have a Platonically “normal” effect on intelligence unless, of course, the individual was protein malnourished as a fetus, had untreated phenylketonuria, or was raised as a wild child by meerkats.”

  10. Great article Patrick! Full of data but still easy to read for a lay-person like me 🙂 Reading about the dramatic shift in height of the Guatemalan children really highlighted for me how important it is to continue with the progress we’ve already made in bringing clean drinking water to every corner of the planet.

  11. Pingback: Buyer’s Remorse | Eightoh9

  12. Reblogged this on russell & pascal and commented:
    Wonderful and complex post. This is my first reblog and it got me thinking. Let me digest, then comment. Wow – – too many food metaphors. Time for breakfast.
    Pascal
    –1:16

  13. I always say that you don’t serve your genes, they serve you 🙂 evolution is about adaptation, so you might as well have adaptable animals instead of hardwired ones that will probably die out if things change drastically.

  14. Pingback: The Net’s Brightest Glitter, from Bonobos to Nabokov | Neuron Culture

  15. Pingback: I’ve Got Your Missing Links Right Here (14 June 2014) – Phenomena: Not Exactly Rocket Science

  16. Pingback: Morsels For The Mind – 13/06/2014 › Six Incredible Things Before Breakfast

  17. This is very good and, it seems to me, part of the trend moving away from the dreaded Selfish Gene dogma. What interests me, however, is how all this fits in with inherited behaviour such as how birds know how to build nests (or not in the case of cuckoos) or how newly hatched goslings know what sillouettes of predators are dangerous etc. It is obviously nature rather than nurture but how does it derive from their genes coding proteins? Just because we only know of the genetic method of inheritance, should we rule out there being any other mechanism?

  18. Pingback: Around the Web Digest: Week of June 8 | Savage Minds

  19. Pingback: A Teachable Moment | The Opposing Thumb

  20. Other “before and afters” I could have used instead of Christian Bale:

    Cristiano Ronaldo: http://time.com/2917803/world-cup-soccer-stars-pictures/
    Sammy Sosa: http://a57.foxnews.com/global.fncstatic.com/static/managed/img/fn-latino/sports/660/371/Sosa%20Color%20Change.jpg?ve=1&tl=1

    Today it’s pretty easy to modify oneself cosmetically, such as through surgery or even something as minor as a change in hair style. For those reasons, I think the Bale example fit well.

  21. Pingback: Science online, warped factors edition | Jeremy Yoder

  22. Reblogged this on Science Itches and commented:
    This is a great post by Patrick Clarkin that I am reblogging here on Science itches. One day I will find the time to really start blogging regularly but until that day comes, I hope you enjoy Patrick’s word sof wisdom

  23. Pingback: Developmental Plasticity and the “Hard-Wired” Problem | Patrick F. Clarkin, Ph.D. - Vitality by Nature

  24. Pingback: 2014 in Review | Patrick F. Clarkin, Ph.D.

Leave a reply to Patrick Clarkin Cancel reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.